Alinsky and Gandhi on Means and Ends The debate about the tactics employed at the Nurrungar anti-base demonstration of a year ago is still raging in the pages of NVT and elsewhere. Although at times this dialogue has been a little acrimonious it is nevertheless encouraging that there is such an intense focus on the meaning and the methods of nonviolent activism. As someone who was not present at Nurrungar, I have no desire to enter the debate centering on the tactics employed there. I have long been an admirer of the efforts of the Melbourne Rainforest Action Group and, because my research interests and sentiments are centred on Gandhian philosophy, I particularly appreciate their efforts at bringing this version of nonviolence-in-action into the public arena (while appreciating that there are other streams of not-violent activism). Although the Burrowes/Doherty debate (NVT#11 Oct/Nov 1989 and NVT#15 June/July 1990) will possibly help entrench already existing views, it will more hopefully provide food for thought for those who have not yet made up their minds and perhaps provide the framework for the dialectical process from which a clearer understanding of appropriate tactics may emerge. The only contribution that I would like to offer to this process is to put a possibly ill-considered quotation, which was supplied by one of the protagonists, in context. Doherty, in his article, points out that both Saul Alinsky and Daniel Berrigan would adhere to interpretations of nonviolence that are quite different from the one followed by Burrowes and MRAG. We are then informed (almost by way of a "throw away" line) that "Alinsky suggests that Gandhi, the great prophet of nonviolence, would have used guns if appropriate." And we are supplied with Alinsky's comment that "If Gandhi had had the weapons and the people to use them, this means would not have been so unreservedly rejected as the world would like to think." In the book from which this quotation is drawn (Rules for Radicals p.39) Alinsky elaborates on the point when he tells us that Gandhi's campaigns "were a striking example of the selection of means" (p.37), and he adds that: History, and religious and moral opinion, have so enshrined Gandhi in [a] sacred matrix that in many quarters it is blasphemous to question whether this entire procedure of passive resistance was not simply the only intelligent, realistic, expedient program which Gandhi had at his disposal; and that the 'morality' which surrounded this policy of passive resistance was to a large degree a rationale to cloak a pragmatic program with a desired and essential moral power. ....If he had had guns he might well have used them in an armed revolution against the British which would have been in keeping with the traditions of revolutions for freedom through force". Gandhi did not have the guns, and if he had had the guns he would not have had the people to use the guns (p.38). We are told that in Gandhi's circumstances 'passive resistance' was not only possible but also "the most effective means that could have been selected for the end of ridding India of British control." Because he could not "expect violent action from this large torpid mass, Gandhi organized the inertia" (p.42). We are further advised that "Gandhi's passive resistance would never have had a chance against a totalitarian state such as that of the Nazis" (p.41). Alinsky concludes this chapter (entitled "Of Means and Ends") by informing us that: "Means and ends are so qualitatively interrelated that the true question has never been the proverbial one, "Does the End justify the Means?", but always has been, "Does this particular end justify this particular means?" As much as Alinsky's work with the poor and disempowered in America is to be applauded, it must be realised that he had a clear political agenda for his carefully selected reading of Gandhi's critics and that it is this, presumably, that causes him to either deliberately misrepresent Gandhi or prevents him from understanding what Gandhi stood for at all. His book is subtitled "A Pragmatic Primer for Realistic Radicals", and his interpretation of the words 'pragmatic' and 'realistic' colours his analysis of Gandhi's motivations. Alinsky, over his long life of activism, developed his own modus operandi but the only theoretical framework that he seems to have produced to support it is: if it 'works' in achieving the immediate ends sought it is good. The ends Gandhi sought were far more ambitious than the ones Alinsky credits him with. Gandhi's interest was not as narrow as merely ridding India of British control, of potentially exchanging white exploiters for indigenous ones. His aim was to bring about a peaceful and just society, a new India and a new Indian. In Rules for Radicals, completed shortly before his death, Alinsky attempts to undercut the position of those who wish to operate in time-frames longer than ones he seems capable of envisioning and of those philosophical opponents who cleave more closely to what can be called the "traditional" Gandhian position that focuses on the primacy of means. The reference to the enshrinement of Gandhi in a 'sacred matrix' is an attempt to preempt any possible response from 'Gandhians' by implying that they or their supporters have not thought through matters to any great degree, that their analysis is faulty, or worse, that they have been duped or are in some way engaging in misleading others. In the words of Pelton, what Alinsky attempted to do was "proclaim that all 'means-and-end-moralists' are strangers to the world of action and are passive non-doers" (The Psychology of Nonviolence p.252). Alinsky's selection, and continual use, of the words "passive resistance", a phrase that was repudiated by Gandhi early in his activist career, precisely because it could give the wrong impression about his very active resistance to injustice, directly serves this end. Anyone who has even the slightest knowledge of Gandhi's life and work knows that the premise underlying this insinuation is totally insupportable. Along with Aldous Huxley, who claimed that "Good ends... can only be achieved by the employment of appropriate means", and that "The end cannot justify the means, for the simple reason that the means employed determine the nature of the ends produced" (Ends and Means: An Inquiry into the Nature of Ideals and into the Methods Employed for Their Realization p.9.), Gandhi maintained that "The means may be likened to a seed, the end to a tree: and there is just the same inviolable connection between the means and the end as there is between the seed and the tree." He added that "They say 'Means are after all means.' I would say, 'means are after all everything.' As the means so the ends. There is no wall of separation between means and ends." And, "if one takes care of the means, the end will take care of itself." Contrary to Alinsky's suggestion that Gandhi started his famous nonviolent 1930 Civil Disobedience movement, focussing on the iniquitous British tax on salt, because he did not have the arms or the willing fighters to do otherwise, the truth is almost the exact opposite. Gandhi felt forced into commencing a nonviolent campaign for the very reason that terrorism and armed violence against the imperialists was on the increase in the country. The 1920-1922 Non-Cooperation Movement, the earlier great campaign of Gandhi's career, was called off by Gandhi (much to the disgust of several of his closest followers), just when it appeared to have some possibility of succeeding, because of outbreaks of violence. (And, incidentally, the defusing of situations that had the possible potential of fomenting armed uprising is one of the reasons that Marxists generally dislike Gandhi so intensely). Gandhi biographer Louis Fischer noted the significance of the 1922 action (the rationale being one that Alinsky, it appears, would not have understood) when he remarked that had Gandhi been nonviolent by a policy of convenience, rather than by creed, he could have championed an uprising that may have driven the British from India: But Gandhi would not purchase independence at the price of national blood drenching; a free India born in murder would bear the mark on her forehead for decades. He sacrificed the end, doubtful in any case at the time, because bad means would poison it (Gandhi: His Life and Message for the World p.71). Huxley notes that the almost universal desire to believe in short cuts to Utopia makes us less than dispassionate when looking at means "which we know quite certainly to be abominable" (p.25). Quoting the line "All men desire peace, but very few desire those things which make for peace" from Thomas a Kempis' The Imitation of Christ, he adds that "the thing that makes for peace above all others is the systematic practice in all human relationships of nonviolence" (p.138). It is the primary means to this important end. Echoing Gandhi, Huxley adds: If violence is answered by violence, the result is a physical struggle. Now, a physical struggle inevitably arouses in the minds of those directly and even indirectly concerned in it emotions of hatred, fear, rage and resentment. In the heat of conflict all scruples are thrown to the winds, and all the habits of forbearance and humaneness, slowly and laboriously formed during generations of civilized living, are forgotten. Nothing matters any more except victory. And when at last victory comes to one or other of the parties, this final outcome of physical struggle bears no necessary relation to the right and wrongs of the case; nor in most cases, does it provide any lasting settlement to the dispute (p.139). Huxley suggests that the golden rule to be kept in mind when ends, and the means to achieve them, are chosen is to ask whether the result will be to transform the society to which they are applied "into a just, peaceable, morally and intellectually progressive community of non-attached and responsible men and women" (p.32) rather than merely the attainment of the immediate goal, of say removing imperialist exploiters. On Alinsky's other point, without going too far into the literature on the question of a narrow cost/benefit analysis of the use of Gandhian nonviolence in the face of totalitarian regimes, the point must be made that in Gandhi's philosophy this question has less relevance than it may have for Alinsky. (The interested reader who may wish to pursue this further should perhaps consult Gene Sharp's The Politics of Nonviolent Action, or Tyranny Could Not Quell Them, and A.Roberts (ed.) The Strategy of Civilian Defence: Non-Violent Resistance to Aggression as references rather than an essay by George Orwell, which is Alinsky's source). Gandhi had a complete answer for critics who doubted the efficacy of his methods against the likes of Hitler, who know no pity. "As a believer in nonviolence" he could not, he said, "limit its possibilities": Hitherto he and his likes have built upon their invariable experience that men yield to force. Unarmed men, women and children offering nonviolent resistance without any bitterness in them will be a novel experience for them. Who can dare say it is not in their nature to respond to the higher and finer forces? They have the same soul as I have. Even if psychological simulation experiments tended strongly to reject Gandhi's underlying premise it still would not have worried him. Gandhi simply continued (and here is the essence of the brand of nonviolence that places such a strong emphasis on means) that "If Hitler is unaffected by my suffering, it does not matter. For I have lost nothing worth. My honour is the only thing worth preserving. That is independent of Hitler's pity." Alinsky's question of "Does this particular end justify this particular means?" is the cardinal truism for believers in violence and advocates of "instrumental nonviolence" - the nonviolence which can be pursued merely as a serviceable policy. A belief in the intrinsic value of nonviolence means that it will be practiced as a creed, and in the Gandhian scheme it is so practiced. Alinsky's proverbial question of whether the end justifies the means is answered in the negative because the view of means as being ends in the making is central to its doctrine. Alinsky is correct in noting a qualitative interrelationship: by using nonviolent means we are in the process of creating a nonviolent future. But then again, even in Gandhian nonviolence it is perhaps not altogether incorrect to substitute the word 'instrumental' for 'intrinsic' if the former is used in a far deeper and more abstract way than is usual for this term in the usual cost/benefit analyses. In short, such nonviolence may be instrumental in the quest for far more than mere tangible political or sociological results. It points to a belief in the underlying unity of humankind and consequently to the locating of the self in the web that is the cosmological order of things. In other words, it may be instrumental in the quest for self-realization. Nonviolence is good not only because it can work to free a country when no other means are available, or because it is the most dependable way of providing the foundations for a peaceful future, but also because nonviolence can work to 'free' the nonviolent individual. And what could be more 'pragmatic' and 'realistic' than that? (I have attempted to spell out this final argument in an earlier NVT article. See "Nonviolence: The Other Reasons" NVT#13 Feb/March 1990). Thomas Weber